Copy part of and slightly amend the introduction of the Deal draft.
This commit is contained in:
parent
cf9230d5fe
commit
97985b3883
2 changed files with 305 additions and 1 deletions
302
deal.tex
302
deal.tex
|
@ -1,4 +1,5 @@
|
||||||
\chapter{A Deal with Life}
|
\chapter{A Deal with Life}
|
||||||
|
\begin{refsection}[bib/sivanov-dblp-mod.bib,bib/sivanov-extra.bib,bib/dealb.bib]
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Life is one of the most beautiful things in the universe. Arguably,
|
Life is one of the most beautiful things in the universe. Arguably,
|
||||||
it is because we humans belong to the kingdom of Life that it
|
it is because we humans belong to the kingdom of Life that it
|
||||||
|
@ -59,6 +60,307 @@ intelligence in no way warrants an extraction of the human being into
|
||||||
an exceptional superior stance---we are part of Life, and we ought to
|
an exceptional superior stance---we are part of Life, and we ought to
|
||||||
think and act accordingly.
|
think and act accordingly.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\newpage
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\section{A short glance on reductionism and mechanicism}
|
||||||
|
\label{sec:mecha}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
In the 20th century, biology was dramatically affected by physics and
|
||||||
|
engineering, and this has brought revolutionary advances in
|
||||||
|
understanding Life and interaction with
|
||||||
|
it~\cite{CornishBowdenCLSA2007,Glade22,Nicholson2019,Woese2004}.
|
||||||
|
Grounding the function of biological structures in the physical
|
||||||
|
reality allowed for convergence of worldview between physics and
|
||||||
|
biology, thereby conferring to the latter the gravitas of a ``real''
|
||||||
|
science. A remarkable tool physics and engineering brought to biology
|
||||||
|
is reductionism---to understand a system, decompose it into parts,
|
||||||
|
understand each of the parts, and understand the interactions between
|
||||||
|
the parts to get back to the big picture. Reductionism in turn
|
||||||
|
fostered the emergence of mechanicism, the modern proponents of which
|
||||||
|
``conceive of the cell as an intricate piece of machinery whose
|
||||||
|
organization reflects a pre-existing design, whose structure is wholly
|
||||||
|
intelligible in reductionistic terms, and whose operation is governed
|
||||||
|
by deterministic laws, rendering its behaviour predictable and
|
||||||
|
controllable—at least in principle.''\cite{Nicholson2019}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
With all due recognition of the major advances yielded by reductionism
|
||||||
|
and mechanicism, it appears hard to believe that this is the final
|
||||||
|
stop on the way to understanding Life. I recall first of all the
|
||||||
|
discussion in~\cite[page~2]{Woese2004} of reductionism as an
|
||||||
|
operational tool allowing to tackle complexity (empirical
|
||||||
|
reductionism), as opposed to the belief that it actually corresponds
|
||||||
|
to the organization of the living matter (fundamental reductionism).
|
||||||
|
Fundamental reductionism makes therefore an additional strong
|
||||||
|
assumption, which impacts the ``sense of what is important'':
|
||||||
|
molecular biology established the molecular level as fundamental, and
|
||||||
|
demoted the status of larger structures---e.g. organisms, ecosystems,
|
||||||
|
etc. These are deemed emergent, and therefore less important,
|
||||||
|
secondary, directly derivable from more fundamental matters.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
While the notion of emergence in natural sciences is fraught, and its
|
||||||
|
objective qualities can be debated (e.g.~\cite{RonaldSC99}), it has
|
||||||
|
the merit of putting in focus the hierarchy of scales. It is
|
||||||
|
a hierarchy in the sense that, while physics teaches us that the whole
|
||||||
|
is always necessarily the sum of its parts (plus the interactions), it
|
||||||
|
is often irrelevant to put the whole away, and only peer at the
|
||||||
|
components. It is therefore important to not always fall through to
|
||||||
|
the underlying levels, and specifically to avoid Laplace's daemon
|
||||||
|
abuse: the Laplace's daemon\footnote{Laplace's daemon is a thought
|
||||||
|
experiment introducing an imaginary creature which knows exactly the
|
||||||
|
positions and momenta of every atom in the universe. The original
|
||||||
|
conclusion conceived by of Pierre-Simon Laplace in 1814 is that this
|
||||||
|
absolute knowledge should entail full knowledge of past and future
|
||||||
|
positions of these particles~\cite{wikiLaplace}. In modern days,
|
||||||
|
Laplace's daemon is often used as a metaphor for absolute knowledge
|
||||||
|
of the minutae of a complex system, down to its elementary
|
||||||
|
particles.} cannot practically exist, but should it exist, it would
|
||||||
|
in no way have any influence on the fact that we as humans find it
|
||||||
|
extremely useful to operate with concepts situated at higher
|
||||||
|
scales\footnote{An informal inspiration for these observations comes
|
||||||
|
from~\cite{Carroll}.}. It is physics again, and statistical
|
||||||
|
mechanics in particular, that recalls this saliently by deeply relying
|
||||||
|
upon thinking about systems such as gasses in terms of macrostates
|
||||||
|
(volume, pressure, temperature) and microstates (positions and momenta
|
||||||
|
of all particles)~\cite{SusskindCourse,wikiEntropy}. In other words,
|
||||||
|
while one might argue that microstates are more ``fundamental'' in
|
||||||
|
some way, it is of little practical importance, and addressing
|
||||||
|
multiple scales is still pertinent.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Fundamental reductionism as a belief is strongly related to
|
||||||
|
engineering, and specifically the practice of constructing complex
|
||||||
|
structures and mechanisms out of simpler building blocks.
|
||||||
|
The multiple ways in which engineering has been durably changing our
|
||||||
|
lives and our surroundings naturally fuels extending its reach beyond
|
||||||
|
human creation, onto living matter. A spectacular manifestation is
|
||||||
|
the Machine Conception of the Cell (MCC) as introduced
|
||||||
|
in~\cite{Nicholson2019}: the cell is seen as an intricate machine,
|
||||||
|
somewhat similar to a computer, which makes it appropriate to use
|
||||||
|
engineering terms to designate the cellular components visible by
|
||||||
|
microscopy: molecular motors, Golgi apparatus, genetic program, pumps,
|
||||||
|
locks, keys, gates, circuitry, etc. The choice of terms is in
|
||||||
|
principle contingent, and it is natural to use words evoking familiar
|
||||||
|
structures, but in practice this reinforces the belief in the
|
||||||
|
truthfulness of the engineering approach. Indeed, scientific papers
|
||||||
|
ubiquitously summarize knowledge in the form of circuits or maps.
|
||||||
|
As stated in~\cite[page~6]{Mayer2009}, ``the typical ‘cartoons’ of
|
||||||
|
signaling pathways, with their reassuring arrows and limited number of
|
||||||
|
states [...] could be the real villain of the piece.'' The Wikipedia
|
||||||
|
page on molecular motors literally starts with the sentence
|
||||||
|
``Molecular motors are [...] molecular
|
||||||
|
\emph{machines}''\cite{wikiMotors} (the emphasis is mine), and
|
||||||
|
features several animations which would look appropriate in a book on
|
||||||
|
the construction of mechanical toys. The last illustration---and
|
||||||
|
probably the most verbose---of the relationship between reductionism
|
||||||
|
and the Engineer's work I bring here is the very term
|
||||||
|
``biological engineering''.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
In fact, widely admitted considerations easily uncover some flaws in
|
||||||
|
the belief in the fundamental nature of the MCC~\cite{Nicholson2019}.
|
||||||
|
To cite two of the most salient ones, the cell is a milieu which is
|
||||||
|
better described as liquid, rather than solid. It is densely packed
|
||||||
|
with various molecules, which do not always strictly respect a certain
|
||||||
|
conformation, but rather continuously evolve across a spectrum of
|
||||||
|
shapes. It being impossible for a human to observe the cellular
|
||||||
|
processes with the naked eye, the researcher is tempted to follow the
|
||||||
|
mindset suggested by the available technology conceived for conceiving
|
||||||
|
of and observing microscopic machines~\cite{Glade22}, a mindset which
|
||||||
|
also happens to be mainstream. Unsurprisingly, if one looks for
|
||||||
|
machines, one finds machines, as the animation ``The Inner Life of the
|
||||||
|
Cell'' conveniently illustrates~\cite{lifeOfTheCell}.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Avoiding conceptual frameworks other than fundamental reductionism and
|
||||||
|
mechanicism not only forces our thinking into a certain box which
|
||||||
|
partially corresponds to reality, but also biases our methodology of
|
||||||
|
interactions with Life. When one imagines the cell as a machine, one
|
||||||
|
expects mechanistic explanations, building upon strong causality.
|
||||||
|
When the computer screen shows a picture or a car modifies its
|
||||||
|
trajectory, it is always possible to indicate a satisfactory set of
|
||||||
|
causes. This is because the engineers who built the device had
|
||||||
|
a specific intention in mind, which can be relatively easily unpacked.
|
||||||
|
Biological systems originated from spontaneous evolution, without
|
||||||
|
anyone human baking in specific goals, implying that causality is much
|
||||||
|
harder to establish convincingly. Yet, reductionism and mechanicism
|
||||||
|
tempt the researches to only look for correlations which may be
|
||||||
|
interpreted as causal: ``It is much easier to write and publish
|
||||||
|
a paper suggesting Protein X is necessary for transmitting a signal
|
||||||
|
from A to B, than one showing that Protein X is one of many potential
|
||||||
|
components of a heterogeneous ensemble of signaling complexes that
|
||||||
|
together couple A to B.''~\cite{Mayer2009}.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
While the Machine Conception of the Cell and similar mechanistic
|
||||||
|
points of view are not oblivious to the intrinsic noise of the
|
||||||
|
respective biological systems, seeing them as machines invites to
|
||||||
|
treating noise as a nuisance which the biological systems manage to
|
||||||
|
successfully combat in every moment of their existence. However,
|
||||||
|
multiple indications exist that noise plays an essential role, as
|
||||||
|
a matter of fact making some processes possible. We cite as an
|
||||||
|
example the Brownian ratchet model of intracellular transport, which
|
||||||
|
has been gaining considerable traction recently~\cite{Nicholson2019},
|
||||||
|
and which essentially consists in hypothesising that molecular motors
|
||||||
|
feature two distinct conformations of the energy landscape---a flat
|
||||||
|
one and a saw-toothed one. By periodically switching between the two,
|
||||||
|
the motor buffeted by thermal fluctuations will tend to advance along
|
||||||
|
the cytoskeletal track it is attached to
|
||||||
|
(Figure~\ref{fig:ratchet-motor}).
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\begin{figure}
|
||||||
|
\centering
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\tikzstyle axis=[->]
|
||||||
|
\tikzstyle movement=[-{Latex[width=1.2mm]},semithick]
|
||||||
|
\tikzstyle landscape=[very thick,cap=round]
|
||||||
|
\tikzstyle motor=[draw,circle,thick,minimum size=3.5mm]
|
||||||
|
\tikzstyle motorFlip=[motor]
|
||||||
|
\tikzstyle motorFlop=[motor,fill=black!40]
|
||||||
|
\tikzstyle motorGhost=[motor,densely dotted]
|
||||||
|
\newcommand{\landscapeXOff}{.2mm}
|
||||||
|
\newcommand{\landscapeYOff}{1mm}
|
||||||
|
\newcommand{\xLength}{56mm}
|
||||||
|
\newcommand{\yLength}{11mm}
|
||||||
|
\newcommand{\graphSkip}{\vspace{-3mm}}
|
||||||
|
\newcommand{\stepLabOff}{-7mm}
|
||||||
|
\begin{tikzpicture}
|
||||||
|
\draw[axis] (0,0) --
|
||||||
|
node[midway,xshift=\stepLabOff,minimum width=7mm] {\small (1)}
|
||||||
|
(0,\yLength)
|
||||||
|
node[xshift=3mm] {$U$};
|
||||||
|
\draw[axis] (0,0) -- (\xLength, 0) node[yshift=-2mm,xshift=-1mm] {$x$};
|
||||||
|
\draw[landscape] (\landscapeXOff,\landscapeYOff) -- +(52mm,0);
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\node[motorFlip] (motor) at (11mm,3mm) {};
|
||||||
|
\node[motorGhost] at ($(motor)-(3.5mm,0)$) {};
|
||||||
|
\node[motorGhost] at ($(motor)-(6mm,0)$) {};
|
||||||
|
\node[motorGhost] at ($(motor)+(3.5mm,0)$) {};
|
||||||
|
\node[motorGhost] at ($(motor)+(6mm,0)$) {};
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\coordinate[above=2mm of motor] (arrowAnchor);
|
||||||
|
\draw[movement] ($(arrowAnchor)-(2mm,0)$) -- +(-6mm,0);
|
||||||
|
\draw[movement] ($(arrowAnchor)+(2mm,0)$) -- +(6mm,0);
|
||||||
|
\end{tikzpicture}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\graphSkip
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\begin{tikzpicture}
|
||||||
|
\draw[axis] (0,0) --
|
||||||
|
node[midway,xshift=\stepLabOff,minimum width=7mm] {\small (2)}
|
||||||
|
(0,\yLength)
|
||||||
|
node[xshift=3mm] {$U$};
|
||||||
|
\draw[axis] (0,0) -- (\xLength, 0) node[yshift=-2mm,xshift=-1mm] {$x$};
|
||||||
|
\draw[landscape] (\landscapeXOff,\landscapeYOff)
|
||||||
|
-- ++(2mm,5mm) -- ++(11mm,-5mm)
|
||||||
|
-- ++(2mm,5mm) -- ++(11mm,-5mm)
|
||||||
|
-- ++(2mm,5mm) -- ++(11mm,-5mm)
|
||||||
|
-- ++(2mm,5mm) -- ++(11mm,-5mm);
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\node[motorFlop] (motor) at (25.2mm,3.7mm) {};
|
||||||
|
\coordinate[above=2mm of motor] (arrowAnchor);
|
||||||
|
\draw[movement] ($(arrowAnchor)-(2mm,0)$) -- +(-4.5mm,0);
|
||||||
|
\draw[movement] ($(arrowAnchor)+(2mm,0)$) -- +(9mm,0);
|
||||||
|
\end{tikzpicture}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\graphSkip
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\begin{tikzpicture}
|
||||||
|
\draw[axis] (0,0) --
|
||||||
|
node[midway,xshift=\stepLabOff,minimum width=7mm] {\small (3)}
|
||||||
|
(0,\yLength)
|
||||||
|
node[xshift=3mm] {$U$};
|
||||||
|
\draw[axis] (0,0) -- (\xLength, 0) node[yshift=-2mm,xshift=-1mm] {$x$};
|
||||||
|
\draw[landscape] (\landscapeXOff,\landscapeYOff) -- +(52mm,0);
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\node[motorFlip] (motor) at (25.2mm,3mm) {};
|
||||||
|
\node[motorGhost] at ($(motor)-(3.5mm,0)$) {};
|
||||||
|
\node[motorGhost] at ($(motor)-(6mm,0)$) {};
|
||||||
|
\node[motorGhost] at ($(motor)+(3.5mm,0)$) {};
|
||||||
|
\node[motorGhost] at ($(motor)+(6mm,0)$) {};
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\coordinate[above=2mm of motor] (arrowAnchor);
|
||||||
|
\draw[movement] ($(arrowAnchor)-(2mm,0)$) -- +(-6mm,0);
|
||||||
|
\draw[movement] ($(arrowAnchor)+(2mm,0)$) -- +(6mm,0);
|
||||||
|
\end{tikzpicture}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\graphSkip
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\begin{tikzpicture}
|
||||||
|
\draw[axis] (0,0) --
|
||||||
|
node[midway,xshift=\stepLabOff,minimum width=7mm] {\small (4)}
|
||||||
|
(0,\yLength)
|
||||||
|
node[xshift=3mm] {$U$};
|
||||||
|
\draw[axis] (0,0) -- (\xLength, 0) node[yshift=-2mm,xshift=-1mm] {$x$};
|
||||||
|
\draw[landscape] (\landscapeXOff,\landscapeYOff)
|
||||||
|
-- ++(2mm,5mm) -- ++(11mm,-5mm)
|
||||||
|
-- ++(2mm,5mm) -- ++(11mm,-5mm)
|
||||||
|
-- ++(2mm,5mm) -- ++(11mm,-5mm)
|
||||||
|
-- ++(2mm,5mm) -- ++(11mm,-5mm);
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\node[motorFlop] (motor) at (38.2mm,3.7mm) {};
|
||||||
|
\coordinate[above=2mm of motor] (arrowAnchor);
|
||||||
|
\draw[movement] ($(arrowAnchor)-(2mm,0)$) -- +(-4.5mm,0);
|
||||||
|
\draw[movement] ($(arrowAnchor)+(2mm,0)$) -- +(9mm,0);
|
||||||
|
\end{tikzpicture}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\caption{A schematic illustration of the Brownian ratchet model of
|
||||||
|
molecular motors. A motor is shown as a circle
|
||||||
|
(\protect\tikz[baseline,yshift=1.2mm]\protect\node[motorFlip,minimum
|
||||||
|
size=2.5mm]{}; or
|
||||||
|
\protect\tikz[baseline,yshift=1.2mm]\protect\node[motorFlop,minimum
|
||||||
|
size=2.5mm]{};), and its energy landscape is shown as a thick line
|
||||||
|
\protect\tikz[baseline,yshift=.2em]\protect\draw[landscape]
|
||||||
|
(0,0) -- (2ex,0);. The horizontal axis $x$ represents the motor's
|
||||||
|
position on the cytoskeletal track, while the vertical axis $U$
|
||||||
|
illustrates the motor's free energy. The motor is hypothesized to
|
||||||
|
feature two distinct potential energy landscapes, depending on its
|
||||||
|
conformational state. In the flip conformation
|
||||||
|
\protect\tikz[baseline,yshift=1.2mm]\protect\node[motorFlip,minimum
|
||||||
|
size=2.5mm]{};, the energy landscape is flat so the protein may
|
||||||
|
slide freely in one of the two directions, with equal probability
|
||||||
|
for both directions. In the flop conformation
|
||||||
|
\protect\tikz[baseline,yshift=1.2mm]\protect\node[motorFlop,minimum
|
||||||
|
size=2.5mm]{};, the saw-tooth shape of the landscape favors the
|
||||||
|
motor moving to the right, illustrated by a longer arrow pointing
|
||||||
|
to the right. When cycles of ATP hydrolysis make the motor
|
||||||
|
periodically switch between the two conformations, thermal
|
||||||
|
fluctuations will tend to push it to the right. (The original
|
||||||
|
figure is~\cite[Figure~4]{Nicholson2019}, itself a reproduction
|
||||||
|
from~\cite{Kurakin2006}.)}
|
||||||
|
\label{fig:ratchet-motor}
|
||||||
|
\end{figure}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Seeing Life as an ensemble of machines biases how we expect to collect
|
||||||
|
profit from acting on it. Machine means control: we are constantly
|
||||||
|
looking for knobs which we could turn this or that way, and which
|
||||||
|
could modify the behavior of the system to fit our needs and
|
||||||
|
expectations. This can be seen both at the very practical level,
|
||||||
|
where bioengineers seek to modify bacteria to produce chemicals,
|
||||||
|
e.g.~\cite{berkleyBio}, and also at the theoretical level, where
|
||||||
|
researchers develop methodologies to support looking for the coveted
|
||||||
|
knobs, e.g.~\cite{PardoID21,Vogel2008,Zanudo2015}. If we admit that
|
||||||
|
the reductionistic and mechanistic approach is not globally true, we
|
||||||
|
must therefore accept that these knobs may not necessarily have
|
||||||
|
a definitive shape, but rather be a complex assemblage of factors,
|
||||||
|
affecting the trajectory of the system in multiple non-trivial ways,
|
||||||
|
and possibly shifting in time. Finally, this control mindset
|
||||||
|
introduces an asymmetric relationship between the controller and the
|
||||||
|
controlled, which is unnatural biological context because both the
|
||||||
|
controller and the controlled are made out of the same kind of matter,
|
||||||
|
and are ultimately embedded in the same environment.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
In this chapter, I introduce the Deal with Life: instead of looking to
|
||||||
|
impact biological systems asymmetrically, surreptitiously lifting
|
||||||
|
ourselves above the living matter, I propose to account for the fact
|
||||||
|
that we act within complex feedback loops, which sometimes end up
|
||||||
|
imposing the consequences of the actions on the actors. The principle
|
||||||
|
of a Deal with Life is to render the interactions \emph{mutually
|
||||||
|
beneficial}: ideally, both systems engaging in the interaction
|
||||||
|
should benefit from it. In practice, this should be translated into
|
||||||
|
joint maximization of a pair of functions measuring the utility of the
|
||||||
|
interaction for both parties, possibly with one of the two functions
|
||||||
|
being prioritized over the other.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\printbibliography[heading=subbibliography]
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\end{refsection}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
%%% Local Variables:
|
%%% Local Variables:
|
||||||
%%% TeX-engine: luatex
|
%%% TeX-engine: luatex
|
||||||
%%% TeX-master: "hdr"
|
%%% TeX-master: "hdr"
|
||||||
|
|
4
hdr.tex
4
hdr.tex
|
@ -82,7 +82,7 @@
|
||||||
}
|
}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\graphicspath{{pics/}}
|
\graphicspath{{pics/}}
|
||||||
\usetikzlibrary{calc}
|
\usetikzlibrary{calc,positioning,arrows.meta}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\newif\ifentiredoc
|
\newif\ifentiredoc
|
||||||
\entiredoctrue % Use this if you want to compile the entire document.
|
\entiredoctrue % Use this if you want to compile the entire document.
|
||||||
|
@ -127,6 +127,8 @@
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\changelocaltocdepth{2}
|
\changelocaltocdepth{2}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\input{deal}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\fi
|
\fi
|
||||||
\end{document}
|
\end{document}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue